Review of:
Slavoj Zizek, On Belief. London and New York: Routledge,
2001.
- "God is dead," proclaimed Nietzsche's madman. Many readers,
particularly undergraduate students, have been surprised by the passing
of God; Nietzsche's implication that God once lived does not comfortably
fit their sense of Nietzsche as an atheist. More than a century later,
Slavoj Zizek surprises readers with his suggestion that God is still
alive and kicking in a post-Hegelian/post-Marxist/post-modern world.
Zizek's project shares many elements with Nietzsche's, in spite of its
opposite account of God's health, including, most importantly, the
interest they share in liberating people from their infatuation with the
Other that dominates their lives--most significantly for Zizek, from the
Big Other that governs the ideological systems of meaning in which our
"choices" occur. Zizek, Senior Researcher at the Institute for Social
Sciences, University of Ljubljana, Slovenia, and amazingly popular
critical theorist, attempts in On Belief to bring Christ
back as the herald of a politics by which the choice, the real choice
(as well as the choice of the real), of meaning can be faced.
- The support for this argument is not easy to follow:
Zizek's
language is brisk, lively, and smart, but it is not clearly structured.
Nor does his style of writing in pithy aphoristic paragraphs lend itself
to broad summary (much like Nietzsche's style). But this book is clearly an
attempt by Zizek to reposition the social meaning and power of
Christianity in order to dispose of a range of social hierarchies (race,
nation, sex, and class, at least); it is difficult to think of a more
challenging yet rewarding political project. Zizek is unwilling to
leave the territory of Christianity to the ostensibly Christian
institutions and interpretations currently acting to maintain the
liberal-capitalist empire. In a way similar to the destruction that
Pauline Christianity wrought on the Roman Empire, Zizek wants to use a
reconfigured Christianity to ease the grip of liberal-capitalist
hegemony. "What Christianity did with regard to the Roman Empire, this
global 'multiculturalist' polity," he confides, "we should do with
regard to today's Empire" (5).
- This re-imagined Christianity, Zizek claims, is the
suppressed truth of Christianity, the liberating power of love for the
imperfections of the Other: "the ultimate secret of the Christian love is,
perhaps, the loving attachment to the Other's imperfection" (147).
Affection for the sins and weaknesses of others is coupled with the
erasure of a final judgment, in part because our attachment to the gap
in the perfection of others is exactly what God loves about us.
Furthermore, this gap is the way in which humans are created in the
image of God. "When I, a human being, experience myself as cut off
from God, at that very moment of the utmost abjection, I am absolutely
close to God, since I find myself in the position of the abandoned
Christ," explains Zizek (146). Because Christ is like us, an
abandoned and imperfect sinner, he is loved by God and by us. "And it
is only within this horizon that the properly Christian Love can emerge,
a Love beyond Mercy. Love is always love for the Other insofar
as he is lacking--we love the Other BECAUSE of his limitation,
helplessness, ordinariness even" (146-7). Thus Zizek's Christianity
subverts the idealization we feel toward the Other by filling this
connection with not our desire so much as our affection for
the empty desire of the Other.
- Zizek's version of Christianity is, he claims, a way to will the
return of the repressed as a symbolic act.
The symbolic act is best conceived of as the purely formal, self-referential, gesture of
the self-assertion of one's subjective position. Let us take a situation of the political defeat of some working-class
initiative; what one should accomplish at this moment to reassert one's identity is precisely the symbolic act: stage a common
event in which some shared ritual (song or whatsoever) is performed, an event which contains no positive political
program--its message is only the purely performative assertion: "We are still here, faithful to our mission, the space is
still open for our activity to come!" (84-5)
Zizek wants to keep this
space open for positive political action. He is the symbolic voice for
the "truth" of Christianity.
- Following the logic through, as Zizek attempts (with
Hegel and Nietzsche on his team), allows him to expect the return of the
repressed within Christianity--or at least to exploit the miraculous
return of freedom and choice in a world where it has been crushed and
exploited by international corporate power. Hegel's dialectic allows
the suppressed to return in defeat as the significant real. Nietzsche's
debt to Christianity is very similar to Zizek's program, in that
Nietzsche often found himself and his truth-telling about God to be the
fulfillment of Christianity. Zizek believes that Christianity can
undercut the liberal-capitalist empire in the same way, by demanding that
the truth be told. This is in resistance to the great temptation of the
postmodern world: that in the way we flit from identity to identity and
desire to desire, we will flit from one logic to another. The truth
should be told. "Thought," Zizek writes, "is more than ever exposed to the
temptation of 'losing its nerve,' of precociously abandoning the old
conceptual coordinates" (32). Christianity can provide the
coordinates by which the ways we understand good/evil, right/wrong, and
valuable/insignificant can be re-coordinated. In this redeployment of
Christianity, through the pursuit of the conclusion of its logic, Zizek
attempts to make the death of Christ stand for the death of the envy of
the Other's jouissance. From this claim Zizek works out a
seemingly endless range of insights and thoughtful observations on
culture, society, and politics.
- One of the remarkable twists to Zizekian Christianity
is its defense and romanticization of sex by filling that romance not
with fate but with accidents and fortune. Zizek inquires at one point:
"What if sexual difference is not simply a biological fact, but the Real
of an antagonism that defines humanity, so that once sexual difference
is abolished, a human being effectively becomes indistinguishable from a
machine?" (43). Sex and sexuality become absolutely necessary to the
continuance of human subjectivity as we know it--a subjectivity that
Zizek does attempt to maintain--not because sexual difference and desire
provide a firm, "natural" foundation but because they constitute the
negative trauma around which human symbolization spins.
The passage from animal copulation to properly human sexuality
affects the human animal in such a way that it causes the human animal's
radical self-withdrawal, so that the zero-level of human sexuality is
not the "straight" sexual intercourse, but the solitary act of
masturbation sustained by fantasizing--the passage from this
self-immersion to involvement with an Other, to finding pleasure in the
Other's body, is by no means "natural," it involves a series of
traumatic cuts, leaps and inventive improvisations. (24)
There is no given to the human condition, human relations, or human
subject. All of what we take to be naturally given to us and naturally
ours--tastes, desires, sex, and loves--are the product of a haphazard yet
skillful "tarrying with the negative." Humanity, like Christ, is not at
home in this world and will never recover her authentic self, natural
desires, or proper place. Our success is our displacement.
- On Belief raises many questions: what,
for example, is the function of the Others that dominate this text,
Hegel and Lacan? In a text that ostensibly attempts to renegotiate the
machinery by which others determine our choices, Zizek spends a lot of
time defending and deferring his insights to Lacan. I'm highly
sympathetic to his defense of Lacan against those who would classify
Lacan as overly obscure, willfully obfuscating, ahistorical, and
ham-fistedly structuralist, but I'm not sure how it fits within the larger
project of Zizek's writings or his attempts to reduce the authority of
the Other.
- Additionally, the selection of friends and foes seems
rather random and chaotic. Why, for example, the apparently
willful disavowal of ideas that Zizek could easily appropriate, such as
Gnosticism? Perhaps this is the inverse of the previous question or a
way to suggest that there are people missing from this book who could
provide useful aides and foils for Zizek, particularly Elaine Pagels
(see The Gnostic Gospels). Zizek ridicules Gnosticism
without dealing with Pagel's work, work that in many ways is very
similar to his, particularly through its emphasis on the absence of a
final judgment.
- Finally, what are the stakes in asserting a monotheism
instead of a polytheism, or more broadly, how are Zizek's decisions
concerning the true Christianity and its corruptions being made? This
reading feels like Freud's Moses and Monotheism, in which
Freud admits that in order to make his point concerning the creation of
racial and national identities he is forced to construct an edifice that
any fool could knock over. These sorts of choices and assertions seem
to be part of the attempt to willfully articulate a new position and
organization for the things that give life meaning, a process that would
be more effective if made less tentative.
- Admittedly, to ask Zizek to play by these rules, by
which his choices are fully explained, is to expect more of him than
anyone else can give, and probably to miss the point that accounts of
the meaning of Christianity really do not have a point of closure. It's
that lack of a point of closure, or determinative point, that makes counter-hegemonic political action possible.
- Zizek knows a thing or two about political action; for
example, he ran for president of the Republic of Slovenia in 1990. More
significantly, as a member of the Committee for the Protection of the
Human Rights of the Four Accused in Slovenia in 1988, Zizek worked to
free four journalists arrested and brought to trial by the Yugoslav Army
in Slovenia and in doing so struggled for the liberation of Slovenia.
The strategy was pursued by articulating a demand to change the
conditions under which the journalists were arrested, which meant a
change in socialism; by pursuing the literal meaning of the commission,
Zizek helped to bring down the socialist government. He is working in a
similar vein here--by pursuing a literal meaning of Christianity, he
hopes to change the ruling linguistic and intellectual co-ordinances of
the fictional rules that govern our lives. By asserting the "true"
value of Christianity, Zizek and Nietzsche seem like the two most
Christian madmen since the one who died on the cross.
Department of Public and International Affairs
George Mason University
cmillerd@gmu.edu
COPYRIGHT (c) 2003 BY Char Roone Miller.
READERS MAY USE PORTIONS
OF THIS WORK IN ACCORDANCE WITH THE FAIR USE PROVISIONS OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
LAW. IN ADDITION, SUBSCRIBERS AND MEMBERS OF SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTIONS MAY
USE THE ENTIRE WORK FOR ANY INTERNAL NONCOMMERCIAL PURPOSE BUT, OTHER THAN
ONE COPY SENT BY EMAIL, PRINT OR FAX TO ONE PERSON AT ANOTHER LOCATION FOR
THAT INDIVIDUAL'S PERSONAL USE, DISTRIBUTION OF THIS ARTICLE OUTSIDE OF A
SUBSCRIBED INSTITUTION WITHOUT EXPRESS WRITTEN PERMISSION FROM EITHER THE
AUTHOR OR THE JOHNS HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS IS EXPRESSLY FORBIDDEN.
THIS ARTICLE AND OTHER CONTENTS OF THIS ISSUE ARE
AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE UNTIL RELEASE OF THE NEXT ISSUE. A
TEXT-ONLY ARCHIVE OF THE JOURNAL IS ALSO AVAILABLE FREE OF CHARGE. FOR
FULL HYPERTEXT ACCESS TO BACK ISSUES, SEARCH UTILITIES, AND OTHER VALUABLE
FEATURES, YOU OR YOUR INSTITUTION MAY SUBSCRIBE TO
PROJECT MUSE, THE
ON-LINE JOURNALS PROJECT OF THE JOHNS
HOPKINS UNIVERSITY PRESS.
|